answersLogoWhite

0

What are the equality axioms?

Updated: 4/28/2022
User Avatar

Wiki User

13y ago

Best Answer

Say there's a relation ~ between the two objects a and b such that a ~ b. We call ~ an equivalence relation if:

i) a ~ a.

ii) If a ~ b. then b ~ a.

iii) If a ~ b and b ~ c, then a ~ c.

Where c is another object.

The three properties above are called the reflexive, symmetric, and transitive properties. Were those three properties all that was needed to define the equalityrelation, we could safely call them axioms. However, one more property is needed first. To show you why, I'll give an example.

Consider the relation, "is parallel to," represented by . We'll check the properties above to see if is an equivalence relation.

i) a a.

Believe it or not, whether this statement is true is an ongoing debate. Many people feel that the parallel relation isn't defined for just one line, because it's a comparison. Well, if that were true, then you would have to say the same thing for everybinary equivalence relation; e.g., a triangle couldn't be similar to itself, or, even more preposterously, the statement a = a would have to be tossed out the window too. But, just to be formal, we'll use the following definition for parallel lines:

Two lines are not parallel if they have exactlyone point in common; otherwise they are parallel.

So, with that definition in hand, i) holds for .

ii) If a b, then b a. True.

iii) If a b and b c, then a c. True.

Thus, the relation is an equivalence relation, but two parallel lines certainly don't have to be equal! So, we need an additional property to describe an equality relation:

iv) If a ~ b and b ~ a, then a = b.

Let's check iv) and see if this works for our relation :

If a b and b a, then a = b. False. But, does it hold for the equality relation?

If a = b and b = a then a = b. True. This is what's known as the antisymmetricproperty, and is what distinguishes equality from equivalence.

But wait, we have a problem. We used the relation = in one of our "axioms" of equality. That doesn't work, because equality wasn't part of the signature of the formal languagewe're using here. By the way, the signature of the formal language that we are using is ~. So, any other non-logical symbol we use has to either be defined, or derived from axioms.

Well, we have three possible ways out of this. We can either:

1) Figure out a way to axiomize the = relation through the use of the ~ relation.

2) Define the = relation.

3) Add = to our language's signature.

Well, 1) is not possible without the use of sets, and since the existence of sets isn't part of our signature either, we'd have to define a set, or add it to our language. This isn't very hard to do, but I'm not going to bother, because the result is what we're going to obtain from 2).

Anyways, speaking of 2), let's define =.

For all predicates (also called properties) P, and for all a and b, P(a) if and only if P(b) implies that a = b.

In other words, for a to be equal to b, anyproperty that either of them have must also be a property of the other. In this case, the term propertymeans exactly what you think it means; e.g. red, even, tall, Hungarian, etc.

So, the million dollar question is, by defining =, are our properties now officially axioms? For three of the properties, the answer is no. In fact, because we just defined =, we've turned properties ii), iii), and iv) from above into theorems, not axioms. Why? Because, property iv)still has that = relation in it, which we had to define. So, iv) is a true statement, but we had to use another statement to prove it. That's the definition of a theorem! And, since the qualifier for iv)'s truth was that a ~ b and b ~ a, we can now freely replace b with a in ii), giving us "If a ~ a, then a ~ a." Well, now ii)'s proven as well, but we had to use iv) to do it. Thus, both ii) and iv) are now theorems. Finally, iii) can be proven in a similar was as ii) was, so it, too, is a theorem.

However, our definition of = only related a to b, it never related a to itself. Thus, we need to include i), from above, as an axiom.

Just for kicks, let's try plan 3) too.

The idea here is to make = a part of our signature, which means now we don't need to define it. In fact, we can't define it if we put it in our signature; because by placing it there, we're assuming that it's understood without definition. Therefore, iv) must now be assumed to be true, because we have no means to prove it; that sounds like an axiom to me! However, just like before, we can prove both ii) and iii)through the use of iv), so they get relegated back to the land of theorems and properties. Interestingly though, iv)makes no mention of reflexivity, and since our formal definition of = is gone, we have no way to prove i). Once again, we have to assume that it's true. Thus i) is an axiom as well.

So, to paraphrase our two separate situations:

In order for the relation ~ to be considered an equality relation between the objects a and b, oneaxiom must be satisfied if we define =:

1) For all a, a ~ a,

as well as three theorems:

1) If a ~ b, then b ~ a

2) If a ~ b and b ~ c, then a~ c, where c is another object

3) For all a and b, if a ~ b and b ~ a, then a = b.

Additionally,

In order for the relation ~ to be considered an equality relation between the objects a and b, twoaxioms must be satisfied if we put = into our signature:

1) For all a, a ~ a

2) For all a and b, if a ~ b and b ~ a, then a = b,

as well as two properties:

1) If a ~ b, then b ~ a

2) If a ~ b and b ~ c, then a~ c,

where c is another object.

What the one right above did is include "=" into our formal language, but "=" is equality, so he actually came up with a fairly well axiom before he finishes with the circular looking one.

His axiom: We say ~ is an equality relation means whenever x ~ y, for any condition P, P(x) iff P(y)

The axiom is the bolded part.

After discussion with my Math prof. this morning, that axiom becomes a properties follows from this more formal definition. It does not need to include any more things then what we already have for the formal language.

We say ~ is an equality relation on a set A if (a set is something that satisfies the set axioms)

For any element in A, a ~ a.

If follows that P(a) is true and y ~ a, then P(y) is also true, vice versa. Because in this case, y has to be a for it to work.

You might argue well the definition for an equivalence relation have this statement in it too, does that mean equivalence IS equality?

No! It's the other way around, equality is equivalence. Equality is the most special case for any relation, say *, where a * a.

Take an equivalence relation, say isomorphisms for instance (don't know what that word mean? Google or as it on this website), we know any linear transformation T is isomorphic to T, in particular this isomorphism IS equality. Of course it would be boring if isomorphism is JUST equality, so it's MORE.

The other axioms in a definition of a relation are to differ THEM from equality, because equality is the most basic. Equality must always be assumed, it always exist, any other relation is built upon it. It is the most powerful relation, because ALL relations have it. (I mean all relations, say *, such that a * a for all a must at least be equality)

User Avatar

Wiki User

13y ago
This answer is:
User Avatar
More answers
User Avatar

Wiki User

13y ago

Reflexive: For all real numbers x, x=x. Symmetric: For all real numbers x and y, if x=y, then y=x. Transitive: For all real numbers x, y, and z, if x=y and y=z, then x=z.

This answer is:
User Avatar

Add your answer:

Earn +20 pts
Q: What are the equality axioms?
Write your answer...
Submit
Still have questions?
magnify glass
imp
Related questions

What is equality axioms?

it is where 3 and ====D connects thus, 3====D hahaha


What are the axioms of equality?

Equality is a relationship that is REFLEXIVE: x = x SYMMETRIC: If x = y the y = x TRANSITIVE: If x = y and y = z then x = z.


When was Peano axioms created?

Peano axioms was created in 1889.


When was Axioms - album - created?

Axioms - album - was created in 1999.


What are axioms in algebra called in geometry?

They are called axioms, not surprisingly!


Axioms must be proved using data?

Axioms cannot be proved.


Which are accepted without proof in a logical system?

axioms


What terms are accepted without proof in a logical system geometry?

Such terms are called axioms, or postulates.Exactly which terms are defined to be axioms depends on the specific system used.


Do axioms and postulates require proof?

No. Axioms and postulates are statements that we accept as true without proof.


What are the kinds of axioms?

An Axiom is a mathematical statement that is assumed to be true. There are five basic axioms of algebra. The axioms are the reflexive axiom, symmetric axiom, transitive axiom, additive axiom and multiplicative axiom.


Does Godels Incompleteness Theorem imply axioms do not exist?

No, not at all. The Incompleteness Theorem is more like, that there will always be things that can't be proven. Further, it is impossible to find a complete and consistent set of axioms, meaning you can find an incomplete set of axioms, or an inconsistent set of axioms, but not both a complete and consistent set.


What does axiomas mean?

axiomas is the Spanish word that is translated into English as axioms. Axioms are concepts that are accepted as true without proof.